|
|||
Introduction To Vedanta - P. Nagaraja Rao 6 страницаcursive reason. One of the great mystics of the Christian tradition, St. John of the Cross, writes, “One of the greatest favours bestowed on soul transiently in this life is to enable it to see so distinctly and to feel so profoundly that it cannot comprehend God at all. ” The Kena TJpanisad declares that “to whomsoever it is not known, to him it is known; to whomsoever it is known, it is not known. It is not understood by those who understand it; it is understood by those who do not understand it. ” What satisfies the intellect is not complete understanding. On the ethical side the Vedantic tradition does not belittle the significance of our universe and life here. Vedanta requires and teaches us a way of life. It asks us to transform the institutions of the world APPROACH TO VEDANTA in the light of our vision. This effort of ours to save- the world without authentic spiritual experience is bound to fail. It asks the God-realized soul not to conduct a sit-down strike and stay in his own room. He should go about his business with his vision and not be tempted by the dirty devices of the world. He should set an example for others in society. The Kena Upanisad declares that “in this human life, we would sustain a great loss if we failed to make an effort to raise ourselves to spiritual existence. ” The mystic poet Kablr writes, “O friend, hope for Him whilst you live, understand while you live, for in life deliverance abides. ” Vedanta never encouraged intellectual indolence, nor disregarded free thinking. It never emphasized piety as against the intellect. Vedanta asks us to begin with a faith that inquires. We should start with a working hypothesis. Faith en- ables us to step out and break away from what is purely empirical. It releases us from the tyranny of the world of perception. Faith gives us the necessary humility which becomes the solid foundation of our life. Its test of spirituality is the increase in spiritual values. An ordered society based on spiritual values grounded in morality is the ideal of Vedanta. The Vedantic ideal is perfect rest and peace amidst cease- less toil and incessant activity. It does not ask us to indulge in the natural appetites, nor does it ask us to suppress them, but urges us to utilize them to build the spiritual life. It neither negates the world nor affirms its autonomy, but only judges it in the measure it is useful to us to live our spiritual life. Chapter V SANKARA’S ADVAITA The system of Vedanta popularised by Sankara is called the Advaita.. True to the traditions of the Vedanta, Sri Sankara declares- that he has derived the doctrines of his system from the synthesis of the triple texts. The glory of this system is that it can stand the test of the most severe logic. Hence, it can be viewed as an independent system of philo- sophy, like those of Kant, Hegel and Plato. It is also possible to see in it the Indian version of the perennial philosophy advocated by the great mystics of the East and the West. The initial authority for the doctrines of the Advaita Vedanta is the scripture. Purportful scrip- ture alone is taken into account. The purport of a scriptural passage is determined by several marks of purport. Of the marks of purport, reason (Upapatti) is the most prominent one. The authority of the scrip- ture is invoked not in respect of those facts that can be known from inference and perception. Where they fail, scripture steps in. Scripture is not taken as authority in the determination of facts that can be known from other sources of knowledge. It describes the two great philosophical ideals mok$a and dharma and the proper means to their realisation. Reason is not ruled out completely. Nor is all reason declared indecisive. It can indicate probab- ility and not demonstrate completely. The Sastras are only jnapaka and not kdrakas. For an intellectual understanding of Advaita we need sharp understanding. It is not for the intellec- tually indolent. The Advaitin believes that mere senses SAtfKARA’S AD V AIT A and reason^ cannot exhaust Reality. To understand the spirit and realise it we need expedience. Spiri- tual experience is the final authority in matters of religion. It is not occult vision or physical ecstas/* Spiritual experience transcends the intellect, but is not contra-intellectual. It is not an instinct. Henri Poincare observes: “Logic alone is not enough, the" science of demonstration is not the whole of science, and that of intuition must still act as a complement, I must almost say as a counter weight or antidote^ to Logic. ” Sankara explains his doctrines with the help of logical reason. He sets forth to explain in terms of logic what he has spiritually experienced himself. Spiritual experience, ‘anubhuti’, is the supreme autho- rity. That type of reasoning which nullifies what is taught by scripture is declared invalid. We find the Spirit by experience and explain it with the help of logic. The doctrines of Advaita Vedanta can be briefly stated in a few propositions. (1) Brahman is Reality (2) The World has apparent (mithya) reality (3) 'The soul is non-different from Brahman* Sankara is a Monist. He believes and posits the reality of only one category. He calls that entity Brahman. There is nothing besides Brahman. All that is, is Brahman. It has no second to it. The Absolute is non-dual. Sankara seeks to establish the nature of Brahman on the authority of Sruti and Logic. In the words of William James, Sankara’s sys- tem is “the paragon of all monistic systems. ” Reality is Brahman. “It alone was in the begin- ning, ” say the Upanisads. It is not related to any- thing for there is nothing else to relate it with. It INTRODUCTION TO VEDANTA is a homogeneous non-composite spirit. It is devoid of all internal and external relations. It is Suddha caitanya. There is nothing like it. Nor is there any- thing real other than it. Sankara’s Brahman is not brute-matter. It is not a substance but is the spirit. It is not a personality with eyes and hands. It is not a system with several parts rich in content like the Absolute of Hegel. Nor is it an organism with several limbs working in co-operation. to keep the organism fit. It is not an object of thought. It is Perfection, Reality and Existence. It cannot be defined in terms *' trf’bhy categories, for there is nothing beside it. It ‘ is hot the result or product of any activity. It is self- caused and the root cause of all. It is an absolute contrast to, and is fundamentally different from things that are. It can only be expressed negatively in terms of what it is not. Here are a few Upani$adic descriptions of Brah- man. In a celebrated passage the Mdndukya des- cribes Brahman, “It is unseen, incapable of being spoken of, ungraspable, without any distinctive marks, unthinkable, unnameable, the essence of the knowledge of oneself, that into which the World is re- solved, the peaceful, the benign and the non dual. ” In another passage of the Brhaddranyaka, Yajna- valkya describes Brahman to his persevering pupil Gargi, “That which the Brahmanas call the imperish- able aksara is not gross, not fine, not short, not long, not glowing, not adhesive, without shadow, without darkness, without air, without space, without sticki- ness, odourless, tasteless, without eye, without ear, without. voice, without wind, without energy, without mouth, without breath, without personal or family SANKARA’S ADVATTA name, unajging and undying, without fedr, immortal, stainless and not uncovered, not covered, without measure, without inside and without outside. ” Thus we see that Sankara’s Brahman is bevond the snh erei of all predications. It cannot be truly designated in positive terms. 1 The negative description of Brahman is not the result of Sankara’s caprice or whim. There are certain logical difficulties in the attempt to describe Brahman in positive terms. It is these difficulties that make Sankara stick to the negative description of Brahman. The logical difficulties are many. To describe a thing is to relate it with some other thing than it- self. In the case of Brahman there is nothing besides it to relate it with. Further, description presupposes some measure in terms of which we describe a thing. Brahman is the measure of all. It is the Reality and ground of all things. We cannot measure the mea- sure itself. We cannot light the candle to see the sun. We can only describe Brahman as not this, as not that. Being the basis of all things, it cannot be described. In a memorable passage the Brhaddran- yaka describes the difficulties. “For where there is duality as it were, there one smells another, there one speaks to another, there one thinks of another, there one understands another. ” “Where verily, every- thing has become the self, then by What and whom should one smell, then by what and whom should one see, then by what and whom should one hear, then by what and whom should one speak, then by what and whom should one understand? ”.... “By 1. Eckhart cried out, “Wouldst Thou be Perfect, do not yelp about God. ” The Tao says, “Cease holding opinions about It. ” INTRODUCTION TO VEDANTA what should one know that by which all this is known? By what, my dear, should one know the knower? ” Brahman is not an object of knowledge. The logic of definition is beset with difficulties. The attempt to define Brahman lands us in contradictions. Defini- tion is a form of relation. It presupposes three fac- tors, the two relata and the relationing process. The predicate of a proposition is supposed to say some- thing about the subject by relating it to it. Several fac- tors are brought to our notice. There is the ques- tion whether the predicate is different from the subject or not. If it is identical and non-different from the subject, it fails to serve its purpose. If it is something different, it ascribes to the subject what it is not. The difficulty does not end there. The nature of relationing which connects the subject to the predicate is discrepant. The ques- tion — is relation a quality separate from the sub- ject and predicate or not — is not easy to answer with- out invqlving ourselves in contradictions. If it is not a separate quality, it is identical; so it cannot connect the subject and the predicate. It fails in its purpose of relationing. If. it is regarded as a separate quality, it needs in its turn another relation to relate it with, that in its turn requires another. Thus, the process ends in infinite regress. If it be contended that there is no need for connection be- tween the subject and the predicate at all, then the category of relation becomes superfluous. Relation is the most important form for the functioning of all logical categories e. g., Substance and Attribute, Cause and Effect, Agent and Action,, etc. Without SAtfKARA’S ADVAITA the category of relation, they do not become intelli- gible. On sharp analysis, the category of relation turns out to be self-discrepant. All descriptions pre- suppose relation and its work. Thought cannot work without the scheme of relation. The relational way of knowing things cannot give us the knowledge of Brahman. Rela- tional knowledge can only give us the appearance of things. Relational knowledge helps us to know about a thing and not the thing as such. It is mediate knowledge and not realisation of the nature of a thing. Bradley clinches the issue about the nature of rela- tions. He writes, “The conclusion to which I am brought is that a relational way of thought — any one that moves by the machinery of terms and relations — must give appearance and not truth. It is a make- shift, a device, a mere practical compromise, most necessary but in the end most indefensible. ” Brahman is above all the relational ways of know- ledge. 2 It is an impersonal transcendent Being that is unthinkable in terms of predicates. It is the seer of objects. The sights are many, but the seer is one. It has no genus (jati), not quality (Guna). It is not a product (kriya). It is above all relational ways of thinking. It is pure consciousness. It is eternal and does not suffer any change (vikara). It is not an exist- ent. It is existence itself. Not being limited by any objects it is infinite. It is identical with the self of all beings. It is neither a substance with the quality of consciousness, nor is it an ever-changing stream of 2. Eckhart writes: ‘‘God is unlike to anything and like to nothing. He is above being. He is naught. ” “God is Being it- self, without a second, unchangeable, without quality, without form, neither this nor that. ” INTRODUCTION TO VEDANTA consciousness. It is not even a subject o£ conscious- ness related to its object. It is pure consciousness, that is neither a subject nor an object, not even the unity of the subject and the object. It is an un- changing indeterminate and subject-objectless consci- ousness. Sankara in his commentary on the Vedanta Sutras writes that when Bahva asked hf Bakshita to ex- pound the nature of Brahman he kept silent. He pray- ed again, ‘teach me sir. ’ The teacher kept silent, and when pressed a second and a third time he said, “I am teaching you, you do not follow. The self is silent. ” The Upani$ad declares that Words and mind returned back not attaining Brahman. They declare that Brah- man is not attainable through discursive thought. “Outside the spirit there is not and there cannot be any Reality and the more anything is spiritual, so much more it is veritably real. ” To say that Brah- man cannot be described does not mean that it does not exist. It is not non-existence. It can be known indirectly and realised directly through spiritual experience. The negative description of Brahman has irritated the critics of Sankara at home and abroad. They equate Sankara’s Brahman with absolute Non- existence. They declare with. Hegel and the Nyaya school that pure being is no being at all. Sankara knew his critics well in advance. He has remarked in his commentary on the Chdndogya that Brahman which is bereft of space, time, quality, genus, fruit, etc. and of all differences is the secondless Reality. It appears as absolute Nothing to men of feeble intellect (manda buddhi). Sankara’s Brahman is self-luminous, unconditioned existence, unexcellable bliss. It is the Reality of the world. It is the real of all reals. SANKARA’S ADVAITA Though Sankara does not believe that Brahman, can be known by the instruments of knowledge, still he does not leave us without sufficient methods for understanding the nature of Brahman. He formulates two types of definitions called Svarupa lak$ana and Tatastha-laksana. The first definition states the essen- tial nature of Brahman. Brahman is described as Existence, Knowledge, and Bliss (Sat, cit and ananda). These are not so much qualities of Brahman as his nature. The description has to be negatively inter- preted. Brahman is not unreality, ignorance, and sorrow. They have to be interpreted in the light of an appositional construction, it would mean Brahman that is Knowledge, Brahman that is Existence and Brahman that is Bliss. There is no distinction be- tween the quality and substance in Brahman. The three qualities, sat, cit, and ananda are not distinct. Brahman is described indirectly by scriptures. In fact, strict students of the Advaita school believe that all descriptions are forms of indirect knowledge. ‘Tatastha-laksana’ demarcates an object from the rest by indicating some accidental qualifications. For example, we may indicate a particular house to a stranger who is in search of it by pointing out to the crow that is perching on the roof. The crow is not an essential characteristic of the house. It only serves to distinguish the object while not being originally relat- ed to the defined object. Sankara takes many of the scriptural statements in this light. The concept of Existence and its relation to Reality is conceived by the Western philosophers differently from that of Sankara. By Reality the idealist philosophers like Bradley mean that which is free from contradiction and is a self-consistent whole. INTRODUCTION TO VEDANTA By existence they mean that which is and is self- contradictory. Existence is self-contradictory. Reality is above it. “Existence is not Reality, and Reality is the appearance of the Real. For Sankara the Reality must Exist. . . Existence is in other words a form or is above all distinction. Sankara accepts the Reality of Jlrahman as a working hypothesis on the authority of the Sruti at the first instance. The Gita clinches the issue in, a well known verse, “ Of the Real there is no Non- existence and of the Unreal no existence. ” What is posited on the authority of the sruti is explained through logic and affirmed by spiritual experience. The central problem of philosophy is to explain the relation between the One and the Many in terms of human reason to the satisfaction of man’s intelli- gence. Sankara posits the reality of Brahman and has to explain the world of matter and the world of souls in terms of it. In fact, he has to explain the relation between the pluralistic Universe of Souls and Matter to Brahman. He holds that the pluralistic Universe is the appearance of Brahman. The indeterminable nature of Brahman is a big stumbling block in the process of explanation. San- kara cannot adopt the theist’s * creationist hypothesis to explain the emergence of the world of matter and of souls as in Christianity or Islam. The concep- tion of creation requires an agent, a purpose and a material cause to create with. All these are not pro- vided for in the scheme of Advaita metaphysics. The creationist hypothesis is based on the law of causation. The law of causation involves a relation between cause and effect. Analysis reveals that the ^ANKARA’S ADVAITA logical category of cause is self-discrepant. The nerve of the argument is as follows: Is the effect different from* the cause, or is it not? If it is not diffe- rent, then there is no meaning in calling it a cause; if it is different, it needs a relation to connect it. We have already seen and shown that the category of relation though very useful is in the end logically in- defensible. Hence Sankara could not accept the creationist-theory. The Nyaya school holds to this theory. They de- clare that the Lord creates the world of things from Atoms (paramainus). The concept of atoms is not free from contradictions. They declare that, to begin with, Atoms are of no magnitude. When two atoms are combined, they hold that magnitude is present. One fails to see how what is originally without any magnitude can produce magnitude by merely com- bining with other atoms. Further, the Nyaya god is described as devoid of any activity. Activity presupposes some connection with matter. It is difficult to envisage any type of relation between the atoms and god. The relation cannot be conjunction, for both matter and god are infinite. Infinite substances cannot be connected. If inherence (Samavaya) is said to be the relation, there is the doubt which inheres in what. Nor can we see any purpose in Lord's creation. The problem of Evil has been the most difficult pill for the atheist to swallow. If it is argued that the Lord creates the things of the world according to the karma of the individuals, there is the difficulty of the supremacy of karma. From the supremacy of karma to the super- fluity of the Lord is an easy step. The problem of Evil and the mad and monstrous contrasts in life INTRODUCTION TO VEDANTA cannot exempt the Lord from responsibility if he is its sole creator. To admit that Lord has purpose in crea- tion is to convict him of imperfection. He is said to be perfect and free from all wants. - He has no desires or unfulfilled purposes to achieve. Activity is a mark, of imperfect souls. So it cannot be attributed to the Lord, without whitling down his perfection and glory. When we examine the creationist hypothesis we are intimately involved in understanding the real nature of causation as such. Causation is a central category of science and logic. It is the soul of all investigation. In fact, all science is the investi- gation of the cause of the things. The Nyaya school is true to v its pluralistic metaphysics in looking upon cause and effect as two different things. They re- gard the relation between cause and effect as mecha- nical. No two things are alike for them. They are radical pluralists. They argue that if cause and effect are not two different things we need not call them by . distinct names. Further, one who wants the pot is not satisfied with the clay or one who wants cloth is not satisfied with thread. The pragmatic test points to the difference. The effect is a new product; it is a de novo creation. It was not in existence before its production. It has come into being as a new creation from its prior non-existence. This doctrine is called Arambha-vada. The Nyaya view of the cause-effect relation is mechanical. They regard change as a total process and the essence of the cause is change. They ignore the connection element which is the essence of causa- tion. Cause is not intelligible except in the back- ground of an identity. Absolute difference is not SANKARA’S ADVAITA intelligible except in the background of identity. All difference is « difference-in-identity. Causation is identity-in-difference. The Sankhya theory of causation is organic. It is a step in advance of the Nyaya view. They re- gard that causation is the manifestation of what is latent into an active operation. The effect is al- ready found in the cause in the potential form. They hold that the change is understandable only in the light of an unchanging element. They oppose the Nyaya school and hold that cause and effect are related states and not distinct things. They criticise the Nyaya view severely. If a thing can be produced de novo from non-existence, it amounts to saying that anything can be produced from anything. Such a conclusion is contrary to and falsified by human experience. It will be impossible to determine any relation between cause and effect if the effect is absolutely a new entity. How could a cause be related to a non-existent effect? Relation can only exist between two existents and not between one existent and another non existent. Further, in our life and experience, we always seek an appropri- ate cause for an appropriate effect. He who wants curds seeks milk and not water. He who wants oil seeks seeds and not sands. The cause itself gets transformed into the effect. This transformation is effected by the causal operation. What is potential- ly present is manifested. The effect, though existent in the cause, is still in an unmanifest form prior to the causal operation. The causal operations take on two forms: It removes the obstruction to reach an object like the lamp revealing the post in the dark. It does not give it shape. INTRODUCTION TO VEDANTA The Sankhyan theory is closest to the theory advocated by the Advaitins. It is the preface to Sankara’s theory of causation. It is the Purva Bhumi to Vivarta-Vada. A little analysis lays bare the self-discrepancy involved in the concept of cause and change. The Advaitin brings oi^t the discre- pancy in the concept of change and causation. The concept of change is as old as the concept of permanence. Let us take an example of the con- cept of change. A the cause becomes B the effect. If they are identical there is no becoming. If they are absolute- ly different we cannot call them cause and effect or the changed object. If change is regarded as partly identical and partly different, the difficulty is not overcome. This fares no better at the hands of the resourceful Advaitin. In so far as the identity ele- ment is concerned there is no becoming; in so far as they are different there is no relation possible between them. The concept of identity-in-difference is self- discrepant. . Though in life the concept of identity- in-difference is accepted, it cannot be logically sustained. The mere fact of their being together is not the guarantee of their validity. Sankara declares that the identical is that which does not change. And yet change must be of the identical. That is the paradox of causation. The cause and effect are identical, now appearing as cause and now as effect. Identity is a basic concept. Difference presupposes it. Identity does not pre-suppose difference. In the light of the Advaita theory of causation we can see Sankara’s difficulties in not accepting (1) the creationist-hypothesis and (2) the transformation SAtfKARA’S ADVAITA 85 hypothesis put forward by the Nyaya and the Sankhya systems of philbsophy. Brahman neither creates the world nor is he transformed into the world. Brahman is an im- partite (akhanda) entity. He cannot be transformed into anything. He is immutable aparindmi and kutastha. The Prakriti of the Sankhyas cannot ac- count for the world. There are several difficulties in accounting for the evolution of the world, the libe- ration of Purasa, the gradation of the 23 evolutes, the bondage of the Purusa, the cessation of the evo- lution etc. The Sankhyan arguments are mostly analogies highly fanciful and romantic. They do not stand the test of logic. If Brahman is to be transformed into the world of things, we are up against a number of difficulties. In the process of transformation, Brahman perforce has to experience all the imperfections of the world. Such a contingency goes against the perfection and the glory of God. God and the World will become identical. God minus the World will be zero. Such an account will make Advaita a variety of pantheism. If it be contended that God is immanent and trans- cendent and that a part of God gets transformed into
|
|||
|